Does anything in being correspond to our capacity for anger?
We all know or have seen animals and children and people of all ages who fall
into a rage over nothing, which is to say that the trigger of their rage is
something other than the event that is its ostensible cause. The rage is inside—fear
the true cause. Fear is unconditioned. We are programmed for self-protection
and for this to manifest exaggerated fear. Overproportioned fear is safer. But
fear relative (or less than so) to the danger is a necessary condition of
knowledge. The extreme of fear is removal from the world. The basis of
knowledge is engagement, overcoming fear. But I stray from the point. Pain and
death are personal. They are the worst that can happen to us as individuals.
But the fear of these is not the source of rage. Rage is characteristic of the
fundamentalist of any sect or indeed the fundamentalist of any ism. The Tea
Party rage, the Al-Qaida rage, the Klan rage. So much rage. This rage is functions
to protect one’s “philosophy,” one’s “discourse” or “world view,” not one’s
mere life. It protects one from thinking, re-evaluating—which is an exhausting
process. (Nietzsche would relate it to power, but that is an
oversimplification.) We have an exhausting catalog of methods for keeping the
blinders attached. What can we say? Rage
erupts from weak causes. Rabies. Neither the psychological cause and the environmental
trigger nor the two together buy this effect. Meanwhile, greater causes, truer
justifications for rage, rarely raise it: actual injustice, murder, rape,
genocide, any sort of violence. Unless one is the victim, unless one’s self is
at stake, one is more likely moved to sadness or complacency or cynicism. And
if one is moved to rage in these
circumstances, it is not because of the injustice, but because one’s self is at
stake. One’s self. Not one’s life, not one’s body. Revenge often kills the
revenger. Rage is always a danger to the enraged. There is much in being that
corresponds to our capacity for anger. But it does not seem that our anger is
ever directed toward it.
Monday, December 30, 2013
Sunday, December 29, 2013
The Puzzle
It's a really clever puzzle. You can arrange the pieces in countless ways and none of them is right and all of them produce a picture (of some sort) and there's always a piece left over.
"A piece?"
Sometimes two.
"A piece?"
Sometimes two.
Saturday, December 28, 2013
Living Incoherently
Incoherence is the fundamental problem. It’s a life problem,
but before that it is a language problem. And it’s irrevocable as far as
language goes. Barthes suggests we eliminate the old bugbear, logical contradiction.
It can take years to understand the necessity. Thinking narratively, we want to
return to a time when contradiction caused little or no bother. We could find
an arbitrary but expressive date for this, but then we’d be too much in the
land of myth. Let’s say that the Cartesian pivot marks an adequate moment. It
doesn’t happen at one time any more than Copernicus happens at one time. It
hasn’t even happened yet in some places. But it began more or less at the time
of Descartes—we could have chosen someone else for this—and has fallen through
time like dominoes ever since, subduing the earth but never the whole earth. It’s
the moment when the realm of knowledge became defined by the elimination of
contradiction—and the discourse of science moved to the front as the model for
discourses everywhere even ones unsuited to science, so that even Freud had to
aspire to a scientific psychology.
That as
I say is thinking narratively. Then there is the fundamental dualism of
language made famous by Derrida and others. This is older and more intractable
than the Cartesian revolution. (I could have picked something else!) Love has
to exclude Hate and God has to exclude Human.
Reality
is far too complex and interrelated and even interfused for these language
systems (however necessary) to work. I heard this week of a brilliant man who
died because he could not grant the concept “altruism” extension in reality.
There are no purely unselfish acts. Christ’s death itself must have had
something in it for God, or why would God do it?
This is
a problem of language. It’s not a problem of reality or God. We have words that
don’t correspond to things, like having a word for a color that doesn’t exist.
(I think all our color words are for colors that do not exist.) We have words
for things that are not things, not only “unicorn” but also “permanent” and “love.”
(People will argue “permanent,” but that’s the point, isn’t it?)
Living
in the world means being uncomfortable in language. Words never do their job.
They can’t. The world is particular and language is general and even 2+2 only
equals 4 within the contexts in which it does. Language is a rough guide at
best. Necessary, wonderful, rough and frustrating.
Don’t
get me wrong. I’m not saying coherence is impossible. That goes without saying.
I’m saying that coherence is undesirable. The closer you get to coherence the
closer you get to living within language alone and not what language sometimes
wants to call “reality” (there is no reality without language of course.
Reality itself is interfused with language) but which we want to apprehend as
though it had no word because it exceeds all words. It’s where God is. (God had
to become the word to talk to us and had to speak the word to made us but has
to be beyond all words to be where and who and what is.)
We make
a fundamental error when we put on a language and step out with no other change
of clothes believing this fashion we’re wearing is the only one there is, that
it is adequate to the task, that it will last through the years. That it isn’t
a fashion among others, that its time won’t go. Atheists proving there is no
God via science. Science is a language that rightly excludes God as a premise.
Logic
is lovely, important, essential. Those who decide without it what is and then
organize their language to create their conclusions have robbed logic of what
power it has. They are the murderers of God. But those who rely on logic can
only God where logic can take them, like the economist who write so cleverly on
the economy of gift giving. In all his talk of value, he missed the whole idea
of “gift.” Or Whitman’s Learned Astronomer.
When you thinking leads you to the conclusion that there is no God or
that there plainly is, the problem is not in God but in your thinking. Shift
the problem of evil.
Language
can help us leave language behind—a little behind, attached to the ankle like a
lifeline as we float from the ship. Cut the rope and we drown. Language can
help us feel what it would be like to leave language behind, like a flight
simulator. Language is always the glass that makes it possible to see what is
outside as it puts a barrier between the eye and the skin and the world. (Even
the eye and the skin are glass.) Break the glass and the world disappears. The
words that can help most, I think, only two. The first is “is.” And the best is
“love.”
A
living incoherence is to be loved.
Monday, December 9, 2013
The Modern Muse
I become more and more convinced that the ancients were right. We don't create art, we don't write stories. We are the place where art and stories happen. "Author," and "artist" are myths of capitalism created to structure payment. Our job is to prepare ourselves to be the place for art and stories to happen. We entice the muses like bower birds looking for mates.
Saturday, November 23, 2013
Freud and Dreams, a further thought
The more I read Freud, the more I am convinced that what he finds clever in the dreamworks and classifies under such headings is "condensation" and "displacement" is merely confusion. He's not trying to decode the secret message sent by the unconscious but just trying to untangle the mess made by the image-making, association-rich brain which in sleep has no aid from reason to help it out.
Tuesday, November 19, 2013
Preliminary Thoughts on Oedipus and Freud
Freud on the Oedipus Complex: People like to talk about this
but don’t like to find out what Freud actually said. The initial description of
what came to be called Oedipus Complex can be found on pages 294-297 of the old
Avon edition of The Interpretation of
Dreams (James Strachey translator, Chapter V, part D, “Typical Dreams”). It
has often been noted that Oedipus did not suffer from an Oedipus Complex. Two
things need to be said about that. 1) Freud never said that he did. 2) If Freud
is right about the complex (about which everyone today seems to have reasonable
doubts at the very least) then Oedipus, if he is an accurate representation of
a human being, did suffer from an Oedipus Complex, though, of course, he didn’t
know he did. Nor did his killing of his father or sleeping with his mother
occur as the fulfillment of his desires to do so. But of course the Oedipus
Complex in actual humans never leads to the killing of the father and sleeping
with the mother. It leads to neuroses. Had Oedipus known Laius was his father
and Jocasta his mother, he’d never had done what he did. The only reasonable
claim is that the play is not about the Oedipus Complex. But again, Freud never
said that it was.
Let’s
assume that Freud was right about the Oedipus Complex, just to see where that
assumption will take us. If so, Sophocles would have suffered from it and so
would the audience. A fictional character, not being a person, need not have so
suffered. But a character who in fact kills his father and marries his mother
is almost certainly going to manifest the author’s unconscious awareness of the
psychological implications of it. Does Oedipus?
Before
answering that question, a brief look at the actual Freudian Oedipus. According
to Freud, the thing that distinguishes Oedipus Tyrannous from all other “tragedies of destiny” cannot be its
treatment of fate, since that is what they all have in common. It must
therefore be that alone among them this one appeals to us at an unconscious level.
And the place where this does appeal to the audience unconsciously is in the
dream-like reflection of the desire to kill the father and sleep with the
mother. Since the audience also has this desire, they will feel the appropriate
and deeply seated emotion that must accompany its representation. They won’t
know why they are experiencing this emotion and will resist attributing it to
its proper source. They will therefore find some other explanation for the play’s
appeal—though that one being false, and unconsciously known to be so, will
never satisfy.
This
analysis has already gone beyond what Freud actually says in the pages cited
above. But it keeps, I believe, very safely within the understanding of Freud.
Here I extrapolate further, but still remain, I believe, safely within Freudian
thought.
Sophocles too will of course also
have suffered from his own Oedipus Complex. And without intending to do so,
would have represented this complex in some way, perhaps in various ways, in
this drama. Where might this representation occur in the play? I believe in three
places. The first is the least important. Believing the Oracle, he runs away
from Corinth. The disgust he feels at the idea that he will fulfill the
prophecy unnerves him. Nor does it make
much sense logically. If you really don’t want to kill your father or sleep
with your mother, then it seems to me it would hard to bring yourself to do
these things. Unless a frenzied mob were going to force you at knife point or
threaten you with the murder of your own children if you did not, it’s hard to
imagine any scenario in which one would even entertain the thought. And how
likely is this sort of overwhelming compulsion? True, one could say, “but he understood
that the gods were behind this prophecy and therefore however unlikely, surely
the gods had to power to make this happen.” Perhaps so, though the mechanism
still seems hard to imagine. But even if so, then acknowledging the power of
the gods to bring about such an extraordinary event must compel the corollary
acknowledgement that fleeing Corinth will not help. Gods that can make you kill
your father and sleep with you mother won’t be stopped by anything you can do. This
means that it makes more sense to see Oedipus’ fleeing of Corinth as an
irrational manifestation of his desire to fulfill the prophecy accompanied by
his disgust at his own desire than it does to see it as a rational decision
based upon an overestimation of his own powers to thwart the gods. In fact it
would not be out of the question to see his fleeing Corinth as a manifestation
of his desire to fulfill the prophecy. After all, he has reason to believe that
Merope and Polybus are not his parents.
And he fails to pursue the question to the end to find out if indeed they are.
He leaves Delphi under the suspicion (or unconscious understanding) that his
real parents are out there somewhere. And if he’s going to get to the business
of killing and fucking, he’s going to have to let himself be led to where they
are.
Second,
the expedient of the solving of the riddle of the sphinx. It’s an essential moment
in the myth, not original to Sophocles as far as I know, but nonetheless
bringing to the play the notion that the solving of a riddle is part of the
reading of the play. Something has to be done to lead the people of Thebes to
declare Oedipus King, and this event has the thematic advantage of doubling the
central action of the play, which is the solving of the riddle of who killed
the former king. At the same time the circle of the riddle expands to the play
itself, an unconsciously plea or opportunity for the audience to comprehend the
riddle of Oedipus—to make conscious the unconscious appeal.
More profoundly, though Oedipus did
not knowingly kill dad or sleep with mom, if he does suffer unconsciously like
the rest of humankind from an Oedipus complex, the realization that he has in
fact done these things is going to determine his reaction to these acts. Here
is where the psychoanalytic interpretation of the play finally becomes
interesting. Oedipus feels disgust at his actions, plucks out his eyes and
makes himself an exile. On the one hand this reaction is precisely what one
would predict for all the reasons that easily come to mind about the breaking
of the taboo. Oedipus’ reaction manifests his own internal accord with the
socially defined disgust at what he’s done, which disgust if already a sign
that everyone wants to do what he has done but is afraid of the reaction of
others. Oedipus’ reaction is a perfectly represented representation of the
personal desire against the social taboo. The society (not the gods) is such an
overwhelming force that even the fulfillment of the deepest unconscious desire can
only mirror the social consensus.
And yet, I find the lack of
ambivalence troubling. I ask a couple questions: what if Oedipus had realized
what he had done and yet been able to hide this knowledge from the public? We
do get a sense of the possibility in the reaction of Jocasta to her own
realization of what has happened, a realization that precedes her son’s. Her
reaction suggests that she might have been able to live with the realization if
the public did not also find out about it. But the public shame (it is a social taboo not a personal one) that
drives her to suicide. Perhaps Oedipus too would have been less disgusted had
he not been publically revealed. He might have exiled himself without also
blinding himself and found some excuse other than guilt. He might also
therefore have manifested some ambivalence toward his own acts.
Of course the problem with this
whole analysis is that it seems to depend upon the acceptance of the terms of
the Oedipus Complex? But does it really. I do not think so. Oedipus is a
character who nearly got away with a crime. The Oedipus Complex is too narrowly
defined to cover the appeal of this play. One does not need it, when the not
even unconscious desire to get rid of everyone who annoys us and sleep with
everyone who attracts us is already part of everyone’s experience. Choosing the
father as the murder victim and the mother as the sexual object merely puts the
desire into its most dramatic form. If you want to get rid of annoying people,
how about killing your own father? If you want to sleep with every desirable
women, how about your own mother? Any infantile impulses notwithstanding, the
truth is normal people don’t want to kill fathers or sleep with their mothers. If
those infantile impulses ever did exist, they do not determine the later
psychological development of the individual. They do not become repressed. They
are chuckled at, abandoned, likely forgotten—erased altogether, without legacy.
The mystery is that though sexual desire is universal we are more likely to
want to escape our families whom familiarity has made boring and whom a
changing power dynamic from child to adult has made uncomfortable, caging. They
may always be fun to visit. But they’re more fun to leave. We want to get back
to our own lives, where we are king and queen.
So in the end, the appeal of Oedipus over all other tragedies of
destiny does not lie in the Oedipus Complex but in the larger family dynamic
and also in the larger human dynamic of sex, power, autonomy and freedom. The
desire to get away with crimes accompanied by a realization of the need for the
laws that define those crimes as crimes.
Saturday, November 2, 2013
The Still Ground
The problem of language is that it shifts while staying
The problem of truth is that like a very clever fish
or freaking fly
it won't stay what it is
for language to catch it.
The overarching unanswerable question
for which you can hardly begin to find the words
for which metaphor is the metaphor
and poetry the vehicle
whose breakdown
provides only the dim comfort of assurance
and the sadness of knowing
it is there
maybe
urging you closer by this
carrying the net of your mind
like a dimsighted guide—
where metaphors
dissolve
and wordless being
emerges
where the still ground
shakes
and there’s nothing
you can do.
perfectly still.
The problem of truth is that like a very clever fish
or freaking fly
it won't stay what it is
for language to catch it.
The overarching unanswerable question
for which you can hardly begin to find the words
for which metaphor is the metaphor
and poetry the vehicle
whose breakdown
provides only the dim comfort of assurance
and the sadness of knowing
it is there
maybe
urging you closer by this
whose words shift
at the fault—carrying the net of your mind
like a dimsighted guide—
where metaphors
dissolve
and wordless being
emerges
shakes
and there’s nothing
you can do.
Tuesday, October 29, 2013
Freud quotation
There is at least one spot in every dream at which it is
unplumbable—a navel as it were, that is the point of contact with the unknown
(Freud, Dreams 143fn).
Thursday, September 26, 2013
The Oneness of All
Rise a little ways above the earth and see
the borders disappear. And then believe
that height is the true height. A little higher
and you’ll see the borders between words
erased as well, tree becomes one with apple,
apple with bird, bird with everything. My love
for you dissolves to nothingness and all
love cries for unity with it and snowball.
Sunday, September 22, 2013
Tentative Thoughts after Reading Ricoeur's The Rule of Metaphor"
I’ve finished The Rule of Metaphor—a book whose conclusions
regarding philosophy and metaphor are—one must use a metaphor—enlightening.
One can take from this work of philosophy an understanding of the
necessary failure of philosophy which is an inevitable effect of the limits of language,
the inability of language to articulate even once the thing the speculative
philosopher desires/attempts to articulate. Metaphor is the conduit from the
known to the unknown. Metaphor always erases what it writes as it writes,
leaving only its trace. The end of philosophy leads to poetry—the next rung on
language’s ladder. Poetry, the cauldron of metaphor, too must fail. The final
step to being is silence. Knowing, inarticulate, smiling silence.
Friday, September 20, 2013
You Are a Balloon
You are a balloon.
Inside you is a capsule of compressed air.
On the capsule is a plunger, which, when pressed, releases
compressed air.
A little spurt and you grow
a little bigger. But
osmosis lets a little air out through the skin.
Your biggest fear is you will aggravate the plunger and
all that bottled air will scream to.
Now.
Boom.
Monday, September 2, 2013
Metaphors of Everyday Life
Ordinary language is the graveyard of dead metaphors.
Ricoeur says as often as he says anything that metaphor is what you will not
find in the dictionary. Thus he draws the line between metaphoric and literal
expression, between those metaphors that have not (yet) ossified into a plain
meanings and those that have. For his purpose this is perfectly legitimate. In
a larger sense it creates a problem in that all the fundamental corpses of
literal language can be (in theory) spontaneously reanimated. We never know if
it’s truly dead or merely catatonic. Whether it is truly dead but can rise as a
zombie. (This carving of a man out of wax seems sincere.) And there are a number
of metaphors at the fuzzy border of the line of the dictionary, passing back
and forth, not quite settling into death or sleep. And finally, for anyone
deeply immersed in language and the history of language, the implicit metaphors
are not dead at all. (I see dead—metaphors. Ghosts.) He laughs at the claim
that the typhoon decimated the population.
It’s in part because language’s dead metaphors are never yet
quite dead to all readers and yet dead beyond recall to others that sentences
are so hard to nail down.
Moreover the study of metaphor yields, eventually, the realization
that the ordinary language we use literally every day to make plain and
unambiguous meanings is really just a collection of dead, half dead, playing
dead and merely sleeping metaphors that create a bizarre monster of meanings in whose belly we live
and which, but for myriad accidents of history, might have been entirely
another monster.
Saturday, August 31, 2013
Reason and Story--and Hamlet
Reason and Story
In one context, the other of reason is unreason, its
opposite. In another, its other is story, which is not an opposite at all.
Unreason exists in the realm of reason. Story exists in a
realm external to reason and unreason. Think of two nonoverlapping circles.
Reason and story are two distinct ways of seeing,
describing, living in the world. From the point of view of the one, they are
mutually exclusive. From the point of view of the other, they are not circles. We
can live here without reason; we cannot without story.
Reason and story are the two ways we perceive, understand,
and respond to being. Reason sees the world as a state that is, reason wants a
hierarchy; story sees the world as a field, a field of incessant becoming.
Reason wants to put the right name on everything. Story sees that nouns are
never quite accurate.
Both are necessary. Story is the name given to the other by
reason. Our perspective, here, in this little essay is that of reason. This is
not a story about the two realms of thought. The same exploration should be
done from the point of view of story. And it has—too many times to name—never
better than in Hamlet.
In the realm of reason, opposites contradict. In the realm
of story opposites exist without contradiction. A man can be rich and poor,
kind and evil, right and wrong.
In the realm of reason, Hamlet is a hopelessly confused
character and a particularly confused play. Reason cannot make sense of the
play. It tries. It is reason’s job to try. Reason understands the appeal of the
play. Reason should never give up the play. But it will never bring the play
into itself.
Story is where Hamlet happens, and story too tries endlessly
to make sense of Hamlet. (Gertrude of
Denmark, Rosencrantz and Guildenstern
are Dead, Gertrude and Claudius are just three of many 20th-century
examples of this, ones whose attempts are more or less direct.) But story is
not anxious about Hamlet. Hamlet is a pool in which story swims.
Thursday, August 22, 2013
Tuesday, July 30, 2013
Why Paint What Is Present?
You’ll never smell the painted rose
I watched a painter paint a scene of beauty—a nude, a landscape,
a starry night—
Why did he do this? It was not to preserve the scene’s
beauty.
What he painted wasn’t there or if there it was unseen.
Did he enhance the beauty with his art or his imagination
What he painted wasn’t there or if there it was unseen.
Did he enhance the beauty with his art or his imagination
or did he paint what was unseen? He added to the scene—yes
but from where did he draw his addition? What absence drove him?
The lover says, I paint my lover when she is absent . I paint from
memory or a photograph because, overwhelmed with desire, I want to bring her back. I
paint to spend time with her. I paint her for the same reason one who
cannot paint stares at the photo or plunges into memory: to make present what
is absent.
That’s a motive to paint what is absent. But why paint what
is present? Why crawl out of the lover’s
bed when she is there in palpable flesh and paint her? I see her better when I paint her than when I merely look at her, better than when I make love to her. That may be so. But is it enough? The painting is also the delay, the foreplay, of making absent what is present in order to make more present what is already present but not fully present. Also true. But isn't the painting also already
about the future absence of what now is present. The future absence that makes
the touching more urgent as the painting dries is the same future absence that drives the painting.
This play of presence and absence underlies all art.
Let's think this through more systematically. Why paint what is present?
To preserve, to enhance, to supplement, to elicit. Those
might be the whole range of possibilities. They all meld together if stared at too too closely. And even if
they were distinct in themselves their borders would be imperfectly
discernible, always in dispute. Nonetheless, they are the possibilities.
There’s no need now to paint in order merely to preserve, if
"to preserve" is aimed at the ostensible beauty a very good photograph (also a
work of art of course) or video would do as much as could be done in that way
more closely and more easily. It wouldn’t be the same—as Emerson noted. The
whole scene is its spatio-temporal context. And that is irretrievable. You’ll
never smell the painted rose. But it is as much as can be had. And so, “to
preserve” can never have more than a small part in painting a present scene.
To enhance: This is never not part of the effect. A painting
that is only as beautiful as the scene lacks something. We might say the scene
can never be captured in a painting, but that is misleading. Something is lost
in the translation. Yes, but something must also be gained. A painting points
at the thing in the scene that accounts for its beauty and pulls it forward,
enhancing contrasts, directing the gaze. This may be enough. But it’s not all.
To supplement, to add what is missing, put in what isn’t
there. There are only two ways to talk about what isn’t there: the absent and
the invisible. The invisible is there but doesn’t seem to be. "To elicit" is to
bring out the invisible. "To supplement" is to add what isn’t there. To
supplement is to commandeer the scene. It’s the imperial impulse. It may not be
wholly negative for that. One wrestles the scene into what it is not in order to convert it into
what one wishes it were or needs it to have been or to be or to make it say what one wishes to say. Lights and filters
and oboes and violins. To supplement is to comment on the scene or to use the scene to comment elsewhere. The choice of
subject is of course already a comment if it is not an excuse (“this is worth painting”), and
everything done from there is also comment, personal or transpersonal: I love
this, it moves me or this is a to-be-loved thing; it moves me or it’s moving. That
general comment underlies the whole enterprise. All range of specific comments
also obtain, potentially: this is why I love it, this is what is lovable about
it, or her. One cannot escape supplementation.
To elicit is the Romantic impulse. To make the invisible
visible. There is always something invisible, not absent, in anything
beautiful. To see through the apparent to the real. God or nothing. This is not
strictly the sign-value of the scene. What is invisible may be unutterable. One
can ache to possess or to become part of the beauty one perceives. The art may
amplify that impulse. It may do this by supplementation or elicitation, and it
may deaden the scene too, but it may also bring the ache to such an intensity
that the viewer—the lover—loses all power to stand. We fall over for lack of
strength in the presence of so much beauty. (Was this the real fall of the
mythic Adam for Eve? Milton may have thought so.)
The painting either leads us back to the scene or takes us
away into itself. Either way, if it is art and not hack work, it leads us to
whatever truth there is in beauty.
Friday, June 21, 2013
What Humpty Dumpty Said
Saturday, as we sat at seder
I sought to borrow Simon’s seeder.
Simon had a super seeder
It superseded that of Peter.
I sought to borrow Simon’s seeder
Because that day I bought a cedar.
I sought to spread some seed around
To spiffy up my soiled ground.
Simon said he understood
And said he’d help me if he could,
“But as it is the Sabbath, sir
And so to such we mustn’t stir,
I suggest you bother Peter
For your seder cedar seeder.”
I sought to borrow Simon’s seeder.
Simon had a super seeder
It superseded that of Peter.
I sought to borrow Simon’s seeder
Because that day I bought a cedar.
I sought to spread some seed around
To spiffy up my soiled ground.
Simon said he understood
And said he’d help me if he could,
“But as it is the Sabbath, sir
And so to such we mustn’t stir,
I suggest you bother Peter
For your seder cedar seeder.”
Tuesday, May 14, 2013
Gun Thoughts
Some questions to answer before you choose to buy yourself a handgun.
1. Have you ever in your life been in a situation in which it would have been appropriate to shoot somebody?
2. Do you know anyone who has ever been in a situation in which it would have been appropriate to shoot somebody?
If the answer to both of those questions is "no," you probably don't need a gun.
3. Have you ever been in a situation where you were glad there was no gun?
4. Do you know of any who was in a situation that would have been improved had there been no gun?
If your answer to either of those question is yes, you probably don't need a gun.
If your answer to both of those question is yes, you should stay clear of guns.
5. Keeping in mind that the handgun you buy is more likely to shoot someone you don't want shot than anyone you do want shot, why are you buying the gun? Is it to make a political statement?
If you are buying a gun to make a political statement, to solidify your association with the political right, to thumb your nose at the left, if you are endangering yourself and those you love in order to feel like one of the in crowd, you need to find another hobby.
1. Have you ever in your life been in a situation in which it would have been appropriate to shoot somebody?
2. Do you know anyone who has ever been in a situation in which it would have been appropriate to shoot somebody?
If the answer to both of those questions is "no," you probably don't need a gun.
3. Have you ever been in a situation where you were glad there was no gun?
4. Do you know of any who was in a situation that would have been improved had there been no gun?
If your answer to either of those question is yes, you probably don't need a gun.
If your answer to both of those question is yes, you should stay clear of guns.
5. Keeping in mind that the handgun you buy is more likely to shoot someone you don't want shot than anyone you do want shot, why are you buying the gun? Is it to make a political statement?
If you are buying a gun to make a political statement, to solidify your association with the political right, to thumb your nose at the left, if you are endangering yourself and those you love in order to feel like one of the in crowd, you need to find another hobby.
Monday, April 22, 2013
Copyright Breaks the Contract
Commodification Is Never Innocent
until they break
in laughter tears astonishment rage
and call to the lyre to play it again
until they know it by heart
until they can write it in air with their voices
until they no longer need the liar and the order of words
he mixed from a town down the river.
The liar with the lyre strums to town
poetry holds the folks on edge until they break
in laughter tears astonishment rage
and call to the lyre to play it again
and again
until they know it by heart
until they can write it in air with their voices
until they no longer need the liar and the order of words
he mixed from a town down the river.
Thursday, April 4, 2013
Christianity and the force of history
It was said in the recent CNN special “After Jesus” that if
not for the conversion of Constantine, Christianity would never have become the
force that it is, essentially that Christianity like all religious movements is
an historical accident that could have been stopped at any number of points had
this or that chance event not occurred—and any number of intellectual
Christians will be suspicious of the claim that God helped Constantine win the
battle; we simply don’t see good evidence for such a God. But perhaps history
does not work this way after all. Christianity was a growing force in the
empire at the time of Constantine, though many emperors and others had tried
hard to get rid of it. Like a bubble rising or a stream falling this force was
looking for a place to emerge. It happened to emerge here. Had Constantine
lost, it would have emerged elsewhere. But it was going to happen because it
was a swelling force in history—a force which the church, for all we know,
prevents like a dam as much as it channels like a dredge.
Tuesday, March 26, 2013
Alarmed
Children used as fuel in woodstoves to heat the house—
Oh well, I thought, in this hideous dream, probably too late
to help them anyhow, though they must be in pain, but that’s the way
we heat our homes these days, and though I went back to reading the book
because, after all, there was work to do, I awoke in a sweat
and remembered—I had forgot to set the clock.
And never the obvious ones
like an image of me failing to set the alarm.
I’d like to know who he is and how he knows so much
and why he keeps such careful track of everything
I’m hoping to lose—like time.
And why he spends all night
shouting at me.
Oh well, I thought, in this hideous dream, probably too late
to help them anyhow, though they must be in pain, but that’s the way
we heat our homes these days, and though I went back to reading the book
because, after all, there was work to do, I awoke in a sweat
and remembered—I had forgot to set the clock.
Somewhere inside me lives someone who knows how to shock me.
He uses images because he does not have words. And never the obvious ones
like an image of me failing to set the alarm.
I’d like to know who he is and how he knows so much
and why he keeps such careful track of everything
I’m hoping to lose—like time.
And why he spends all night
shouting at me.
Monday, March 25, 2013
The Sensor in the Ceiling
The sensor in my ceiling is watching me
It wants me to move.
If I do not obey, it will throw me into darkness.
It’s like a cowboy shooting bullets at my feet
To make me dance.
Saturday, March 23, 2013
Closed Form Poem
by Alan Lindsay
This is a closed form poem. The rhythm
is invariable. It does not rhyme.
But the third line has to be
enjambed and the fifth line always begins with the word
yellow. I am sorry. You cannot alter the subtle play of vowels.
The glottal stops, the fricatives—all stay the same.
Also caesura, strategically deployed. You cannot change
the words, or the order of the words or any of the line
breaks. The form is locked tight as a drum or painter’s canvas.
I have created the form. It is mine.
How can you make the poem your own?
You can change the name beneath the title.
That name is not part of the poem and does not belong
to the form. You can tack the poem to a tree
deep in the woods, overlooking a stream. You can place the poem
on a pole in a field above the swaying grass, above the gazing grain.
You can tattoo the poem to your breast and embarrass men by asking them
to read it to the final period. You can recite it before crowds on New York City streets
hurrying to work with cardboard cups of Starbucks in their free hands.
Thursday, March 21, 2013
Why would that be?
Reality gives us too little to think about, too little
stimulation for the brain, so we create puzzles and literature and math and
physics. They keep our brains busy, our minds from imploding. They satisfy our
craving to be curious. But why would evolution spend the resources necessary to
create a being dissatisfied with survival? Nature’s principle for success is
excess: cast millions of seeds in the expectation of a dozen trees. Create a
universe whose size exceeds all image or metaphor in the hope (if hope is part
of the universe) of a handful of planets capable of sustaining life and of
creatures capable of looking back at it and saying “what?” Because if it make
sense to say that the universe is for anything, that is what it is for.) Any God this universe has is not interested in
efficient manufacture. Why would that
be?
Tuesday, February 26, 2013
A reconsideration of Wittgenstein’s “Family Resemblances” and “Language Games.”
What baffled Wittgenstein was his inability to define “games,”
a simple concept, easily understood, but which defies the impulse of the
dictionary. I have no interest in defining games. But I am very interested in
his bafflement. There’s nothing special about a word that cannot be defined.
What would be interesting would be a word that can be defined. What’s
fascinating is the fact that anyone ever thought up the concept of dictionary,
which is the legacy of Platonism, which got everything backwards. How much of
history and philosophy and just thinking has been confused by the idea that meaning
is something that words have rather than something, as every poet knows, that
we use words to produce: always in time, at a moment in history. The moment
stretches and changes through memory and writing (which is any form of
recording) forward (Shakespeare would have said “backward”) into time. But
meaning only ever exists at a moment, the moment of saying, the moment of
hearing (writing/reading). We want to be as precise as possible, but not based
on the meaning of the word, based rather on the history of the use of the word—the
contexts in which it has been used to create meaning. The presupposition that
meaning exists always already “out there,” and that our job is to find it,
inscribe it, and pass it on is a metaphor less accurate and less useful than
the metaphor deployed here, that words are used to inscribe meanings available
but never yet accessed in language, by novel combinations of words. What is “out
there” is the pressure of “being” at this moment on the writer (thankfully, me)
to reassemble the words to settle for now the image whose formulation is
functional, which makes our present make better sense. Since words like “game”
(and all other words, those that obviously defy definition—poetry and history
and love and nation and person and on and on—and those that we think do not) mean
only in moments, then all uses are stipulative. And so in a moment of use “game”
have have all the precision of the number “2”’ and “2” all the vagueness of the
concept “nice.” And what’s surprising is that it is surprising.
Sunday, February 24, 2013
The Paradox of Memory
Memory is fallible.
Every time you access a memory you change it.
To retain a memory you must access it often.
The more vividly you remember a long-ago event the less
accurate that memory is.
The passion then that became your being is therefore now more
metaphor than substance.
True only as metaphors are true.
True only as metaphors are true.
If the goal is an accurate account of an event, recording
works best. You can put it down just then and put it away and never think about
it--until, years later, you stumble upon your image of this forgotten time and
read it like a story, one you feel you may have read before, recalling each line as
it emerges, unable to anticipate what’s next, as though the account you are
reading is of something that happened to someone else.
Which it is.
It is always the destiny of history to be resurrected
as story.
Saturday, February 23, 2013
Murphy's Law and Gun Control
I don’t know the origin of Murphy’s law. I suppose the
origin is only a google away, but it doesn’t matter. The law itself states, as
we all know, “anything that can go wrong, will go wrong,” with a sometimes corollary,
“at the worst possible time.” The corollary is clearly a late add-on, intended
to intensify the perceived cynical joke that is the heart of the law. But the
law itself, though comically formulated, is in fact a law. Better stated, “Anything
that can happen, will happen, given enough time.” It explains why intelligent
life showed up in the universe despite the extraordinary chances against it (by
the reckoning of some). The universe is that big and that old and given certain
conditions it is possible. It tells us also, then, that even if we were to
eliminate all causes of death except one—let’s say car accidents—then
eventually everyone will die in a car accident. Much could be accomplished if
we were to simply keep Murphy’s law more prominently in mind when we do such
things as build nuclear power plants and put in place ample safeguards to insure against
meltdown. There are not enough safeguards in the universe to insure against
meltdown. Or when we argue about gun control: no law (as the right wing always reminds us)
will prevent random slaughter. Or when we put locks on houses: no lock will
prevent unwanted access. Safeguards and locks and laws are all means of
reducing chances, lowering percentages.
That doesn’t mean they are useless.
Sunday, February 17, 2013
More on Time and Language and Borges and Nietzsche
Borges’ “New Refutation of Time,” and Nietzsche’s “Eternal
Return,” rest on the same thing (for “thing” we could read “fact” or “error”):
that the world of language has no way of conceptualizing the world of
experience that can fit into itself (that can “comprehend”) time. Our system of
concepts as well as our vocabulary is too poor. We simply cannot say what we
intuit regarding time in an irrefutable fashion.
A close look at Borges’ essay reveals how tricky the problem
is: is it according to experienced that time exists or according to
intellection? Experience tells us both
that time exists and that time does not exist. Borges walks down the streets
around his old neighborhood. One moment succeeds another. He stops at a wall,
I kept looking at this simplicity.
I thought…: This is the same as thirty years ago… Perhaps a bird was singing and
for it I felt a tiny affection, the same size as the bird; but the most certain
thing was that in this now vertiginous silence there was no other sound than
the intemporal one of the crickets. The easy thought ‘I am in the
eighteen-nineties’ cased to be a few approximate words and was deepened into a
reality. I felt dead, I felt as an abstract spectator of the word; an
indefinite fear…. I did not fear that I had returned upstream on the supposed
waters of Time; rather I suspected that I was the possessor of a reticent or
absent sense of the inconceivable word eternity.
It is the same thing expressed by Keats, “Thou wast not born
for death immortal bird.” Borges also experiences this eternity, as do we all,
he tells us, in music and other “human moments,” such as suffering and
pleasure, moments repeated exactly from one person to another, moments, we
might add (contra Bakhtin) that are the basis for art and language, when
identity fades and different experiences lose their difference.
Time is experienced as successive and eternal, as existing
and as not existing. In language it is posited as the only explanation for
phenomena and yet it is uncapturable, inexpressible. It must be posited because
it cannot be shown to exist at all. (To call it “self-evident” is to say the
same thing in a disingenuous way, trying to erase the very problem—not visible
to language.) Time’s existence and time’s nonexistence are both part of both
language and experience, but as four nonoverlapping circles.
This cannot imply that our experience is true and our
intelligence is false. But it does mean that we have to choose which to accept
before we can choose how to respond. (How could one stay neutral here?) Let’s
choose, provisionally, momentarily, experience over language not for no reason,
but only because it’s more interesting to do so. It leaves us more to say.
This problem of the inadequacy of language to its presumed object
is of course not limited to the comprehension of time. This inadequacy of
language to match experience (subjectivity) or the world (objectivity) accounts
for the whole being and frustration of philosophy as well as literature. It’s
demonstrable, for example, of the infamous cogito,
the so-called foundational statement of modern philosophy. The statement itself
has become ragged for all the darts tossed at it: I think, therefore I am. In
its favor, it functions as well as statement can to capture the experience of
being. But it does not make logical sense—it fails in terms of language. So
here’s the point: contradiction is the sine
qua non of statement. Go back through these very paragraphs and graph the
contradictions.
In his “New Refutation,” Borges makes the marvelous statement
that night pleases because it “suppresses idle details, just as memory does.”
Reading—in fact any comprehension of language—requires darkness as well as
light. All coherence, all meaning, is washed out if the reader comprehends the
full scope of every word. Every word is a potential metonymy. And every
statement is a riddle of contradictions that must be ignored for the reception
of the thread meaning that runs through it under the fabric of noise. All understanding
requires the good faith and hard work of the receiving brain.
Saturday, February 16, 2013
Wednesday, February 6, 2013
Sunday, February 3, 2013
My Dearest John
Please,
stop loving me.
It’s distracting.
Oh, I’m not saying you don’t do an admirable job
smiling and chatting
and walking nonchalantly away,
but that smile and that catch in your chat
and those eyes that affix my eyes
so I can’t duck or nod or turn
my head. I want to spend a night in bed
without this stone in my chest.
Is that too much to ask?
I want to walk outdoors on a cool spring morning and
feel the world’s effervescence
without howling.
Stop reminding me about Paris. Stop asking
if I’m okay. (I’m not, okay?) Stop telling me you
have a free hour
every Thursday after lunch.
Stop running past my window
in your cleverly reflective running shorts
and matching shoes. I’m here,
but I won’t tell you.
Dear John, somewhere
someone has days
she can’t get through
because of what she thinks when she thinks
of you. Dear John,
I don’t care that the past can never be put away,
That what it will
have been is always yet to be determined.
I do not care.
This has to end.
Love,
Jane
Thursday, January 31, 2013
Redeeming the Past
"The past can never be put away because what it will have been is always yet to be determined."
One theological difficulty I've long had has been the problem of redemption. An event happens, an evil event, how can that event be redeemed? How can the evil be erased? It cannot be made not to have happened. It can't be defined away. What amount of "good" and of what type pays for it? It's not a question of a willingness to accept payment in lieu of justice--as happens endlessly in the courts. Nor is it the idea that "if we do this good thing than that bad thing will not have been in vain." It may be that it was not in vain. But was it ever paid for? Can you ever say "I'd rather have the good that came out of my child's death than the for the child not to have died." The good doesn't pay back the evil no matter how good it is. The whole economic metaphor breaks down because payment is made in an unconvertible currency. The bad thing was evil, the good that it was transformed into was good. But that legerdemot that allows us to substitute "evil" for the event doesn't fool anyone. Much more needs to be said here.
But the next step in thought is what I have quoted above. The event itself has never stopped happening, whatever it was. The past has never sat still. What it was is always changing. And in this lies the hope for the redemption of the past. In principle, if a tragedy can be ameliorated by a subsequent love, then is it possible for enough love to redeem it? The goal is not to make it to have been okay, but to make it no longer to have been evil. If any degree of evil can be erased, then the whole can be overcome. Much more needs to be said.
One theological difficulty I've long had has been the problem of redemption. An event happens, an evil event, how can that event be redeemed? How can the evil be erased? It cannot be made not to have happened. It can't be defined away. What amount of "good" and of what type pays for it? It's not a question of a willingness to accept payment in lieu of justice--as happens endlessly in the courts. Nor is it the idea that "if we do this good thing than that bad thing will not have been in vain." It may be that it was not in vain. But was it ever paid for? Can you ever say "I'd rather have the good that came out of my child's death than the for the child not to have died." The good doesn't pay back the evil no matter how good it is. The whole economic metaphor breaks down because payment is made in an unconvertible currency. The bad thing was evil, the good that it was transformed into was good. But that legerdemot that allows us to substitute "evil" for the event doesn't fool anyone. Much more needs to be said here.
But the next step in thought is what I have quoted above. The event itself has never stopped happening, whatever it was. The past has never sat still. What it was is always changing. And in this lies the hope for the redemption of the past. In principle, if a tragedy can be ameliorated by a subsequent love, then is it possible for enough love to redeem it? The goal is not to make it to have been okay, but to make it no longer to have been evil. If any degree of evil can be erased, then the whole can be overcome. Much more needs to be said.
Language and the NRA
If this is a blog about language, then it's impossible not to comment on the language of the NRA. Two things: the mantra-like argument that makes one's ears bleed: "The problem is large and complex. And these new restrictions will not solve it." A statement of fact--that doesn't address the question it pretends to address. A response to an argument the other side never made. Yes, the problem is large and complex. And certainly new gun laws are, in relation to the scope of the problem, small. But large, complex problems do not often admit of simple solutions. New gun laws aren't meant to SOLVE the problem. They ADDRESS the problem. They are one facet of a comprehensive solution that people of good will, be there such people on both sides, work out together. The only sensible response of the NRA and its supporters would be, "I don't believe this will help much if at all. But it's also not much of a sacrifice. No one needs military weapons. No one needs 100 round clips. If giving these up allows us to move on, we'll do that, because the goal to see that no more people die in these massacres. And if we don't take the first step, we'll never get to the second step. And anyway, no sane person would suggest that these laws make the world more dangerous." But of course they don't. They stall and preach an absurdist reading of the second amendment and make clear their primary interest is not life or law or order but the free right to guns of all kinds.
Second, behind the effectiveness of this childish argument lies a perverse (one is tempted to say insane) reading of the second amendment. No great effort is required to discover that the second amendment exists because Washington and company did not want the U.S. to have a standing army. They wanted a people's army. Because of real threats from foreign powers, the government was willing to risk the dangers of having weapons in the hands of citizens so they could call on those citizens at a moment's notice and not have to go through the trouble or expense of buying guns for a whole army. (There was no factory production of guns in 1780.) The purpose of the second amendment was to prevent the U.S. from having a standing army. It was a backdoor strategy. The very text reveals the forces of contention from which these words emerged.
The amendment in the end is somewhat cowardly and even cynical. Yes, it says, we know that there will be violence out there among the people. Intelligent people are aware that a country full of armed citizens is a minefield. We will lose good people, innocent citizens because of this law. But the trade off is security for the whole nation. And we'll take that--because we do not want an army. We do not want a force that could sweep in and challenge the civilian government.
All of that is forgotten in this debate (which is more a shouting match than a debate). Even the Supreme Court with its "original intentionists," pretend that the amendment simply guarantees every citizen a right to a gun for SELF-defense. The "militia" clause is erased. The intention which in this case is clear and available is simply ignored. And the nation becomes more militarized as it becomes more polarized.
If the people are out buying more and more guns simply because they don't like the elected president, we have a huge and complex problem, not one that can be solved or addressed by maintaining liberal gun laws.
Second, behind the effectiveness of this childish argument lies a perverse (one is tempted to say insane) reading of the second amendment. No great effort is required to discover that the second amendment exists because Washington and company did not want the U.S. to have a standing army. They wanted a people's army. Because of real threats from foreign powers, the government was willing to risk the dangers of having weapons in the hands of citizens so they could call on those citizens at a moment's notice and not have to go through the trouble or expense of buying guns for a whole army. (There was no factory production of guns in 1780.) The purpose of the second amendment was to prevent the U.S. from having a standing army. It was a backdoor strategy. The very text reveals the forces of contention from which these words emerged.
The amendment in the end is somewhat cowardly and even cynical. Yes, it says, we know that there will be violence out there among the people. Intelligent people are aware that a country full of armed citizens is a minefield. We will lose good people, innocent citizens because of this law. But the trade off is security for the whole nation. And we'll take that--because we do not want an army. We do not want a force that could sweep in and challenge the civilian government.
All of that is forgotten in this debate (which is more a shouting match than a debate). Even the Supreme Court with its "original intentionists," pretend that the amendment simply guarantees every citizen a right to a gun for SELF-defense. The "militia" clause is erased. The intention which in this case is clear and available is simply ignored. And the nation becomes more militarized as it becomes more polarized.
If the people are out buying more and more guns simply because they don't like the elected president, we have a huge and complex problem, not one that can be solved or addressed by maintaining liberal gun laws.
Thursday, January 10, 2013
Oz House or OzHouse (never Oz-House)... It's getting hot in there....
http://www.amazon.com/Oz-House-ebook/dp/B008YTUW2U/ref=sr_1_1?ie=UTF8&qid=1357867109&sr=8-1&keywords=oz+house+lindsay
Newly published. A fun frolic through fairy stories and lands.
Newly published. A fun frolic through fairy stories and lands.
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)